Perhaps all representation is doomed to fail. It is a troubling idea, but seems possible, and even inevitable. Perhaps the hegemonic underpinnings of representations in their most basic form, language, prevent us from ever truly achieving objectivity in representation. That seems to be the aim of representation, after all. Accurate representation is objective truth. But perhaps this is unachievable. If this is all true, how are we to function in such a world?
Heibrun’s main concern was a
lack of a female canon in literature. There was not past, no history of true
female readers to set an example for future woman writers. Gilbert and Gubar
call this anxiety of authorship. While male writers experience and anxiety of
invention, a desire to be more inventive and more successful than those who
came before them, women have no foundation to build upon. There were no women
writers who came before them. Their primary anxiety involved authorship in its
most basic form. It was an anxiety of creating something and publishing
something that was an extension—a representation—of themselves and women.
Butler then raises a
related, but very troubling, concern. Is it possible that women are
unrepresentable? And that a canon that truly and accurately represents female
writers is impossible? If, as Butler assets, our entire notion of feminism is
powered by our understanding of women
as a unified, generalized, misrepresented group, the foundation of the ideology
is flawed. Feminism seeks to recognize and support women as a whole. But in
doing so, feminists ignore all other intricacies of the female individual.
These individuals are united into the category of women solely because they are
women. Race, ethnicity, socioeconomic class, and so on are all ignored. We thus
acknowledge them as nothing but their gender. This presents a problem. Isn’t
this the very generalizing and lumping together of females that feminists seek
to transcend.
Butler asserts that the “presumed universality and
unity of the subject of feminism is effectively undermined by the constraints
of the representational discourse in which it functions” (Butler 6). We strive
to represent women accurately but the representational discourse surrounding
women fails from the start. The problem lies in language. When the very
language that we use in our everyday lives is laden with misrepresentation, how
can we ever hope to achieve accurate representation?
Professor
Graban suggested that this is perhaps and issue of privilege, of hegemony. This
makes perfect sense. There is no doubt that it is the privileged individuals of
the world who create and propagated knowledge, culture, understanding, and
rules. They determine how things are to be represented from the very beginning.
They create and mold language. Take, for instance, our culture. Our language,
our understanding of ideas and of words is heavily influenced by the abled,
white, male hand. The problem does not lie in the misuse of representations,
but rather the fault in representations from their very inceptions. Language is
representation and words are symbols. When a word carries hegemonic history, as
all words do, the biases of the hegemonic powers are implicit to the definition
and understanding of the world. We may not notice or realize this, but it is
undoubtedly true.
This all
suggests something quite troubling for representation. When hegemonic
misrepresentations are implicit to our representations, unbeknownst to us, is
it ever possible to accurately represent anything? It is clear that this is a
problem in the case of the female, as Butler argues. But, let us take a step
back and look at the whole picture. If our language fails at objectivity, to it’s
very core, and language is our primary means of representation, our
representations must fail us as well. Does this mean that we cannot ever truly
represent anything ever? Are all people, all cultures, all of the world unrepresentable?
While we
didn’t read Butler’s book in it’s entirety, Professor Graban hints that a
solution might exist in reexamining how we understand—how we represent—representation.
Perhaps we are relying on representation too heavily. Perhaps representation shouldn't and can't be expected to reveal objective truth. We expect it to be bale
to paint a clear and vivid picture of the truth. Perhaps this is wrong. With
all of it’s faults, we can never rely on representation to function objectively
in this way. We must, instead, take with it it’s biases. Recognize the
hegemonic, privileged underpinnings and work around them. It is merely a matter
of acknowledging inevitable terministic screens.
I also wrote about the fundamental issues with representation, and I really enjoyed how you pointed out that problems with representation may stem from the hegemony of cultures, races, and gender over language, influencing our understanding of words. I agree that representation shouldn't be expected to 'reveal objective truth', and that we must examine other factors that influence representation.
ReplyDelete