Self-reflexivity encompasses a lot of factors based on the
genre and the given substrate of a text or a work. Self-reflexivity in
accordance with metapictures has the ability to “make visible the impossibility
of a strict metalanguage, a second-order representation that stands free of its
first-order target,” (Mitchell 83). As a whole, self-reflexivity possess both
formal and structural qualities of the first and secondary variety. In Metapictures, W. J. T. Michell examines
three unique examples where metatextuality, metapictures, and self-reflexivity
come together. My aim is to further elaborate on the subject of metapictures
and metatext as they relate to one another in the exploration of metatextuality
in regards to self-reflexivity and how it varies from one substrate, genre, and
context to the next.
To begin, self-reflexivity in itself can be defined as a
text or work of art directly becoming metatextual and metapictorial, as W. J.
T. Mitchell defines it. It is more than just art for arts sake, making a point
to bring attention to itself within a given frame. For example, “self reference
is the uniting theme for accounts of modern art that might seem, at first
glance, to be radically opposed,” adding to the fact that self-reflexivity in
its most basic concept is actually more of a paradigm than one would imagine, (Mitchell
36). The reason being that art is not meant to draw attention to itself, but
rather is to be used as a means of analysis or a deeper meaning than what can
be seen on the surface. However, when art changes, and becomes self-reflexive
it is almost like art itself is no longer art, but more of a critique of
itself, through the formal qualities that it undergoes to become self-reflexive
in the first place. As previously stated, this is a concept that can vary from
substrate, to genre, to context.
Next, “a “medium” could be understood to include all those determining
conditions,” (Mitchell 36). By medium, we can begin to include different
substrates. Different substrates will be more self-reflective than others. With
the case of Mitchell’s text, he directly addresses three examples: Steinberg’s
The Spiral, Alain’s “Egyptian Life
Class”, and Jastrow’s “The Duck-Rabbit. These are outstanding examples of
metapictorial occurrences, but are not exactly metatextual in the formal way
that the term would be defined. What I mean by that is when given a specific
medium, the message of a given text will change. For instance, hypertext has
the ability to be self-reflective, and even interactive with itself to an
extent. Different readers, and different viewers will take advantage of
hypertext’s self-reflexive qualities in a different manner. A various range of
multimedia platforms also have the ability to be self-reflexive, it just
depends on the ability of the user and the manner in which they are utilized;
this can include blogging and even social media.
With regards to genre, the aim with metatextual and metapictorial
elements is to compartmentalize “the problem of […] self-reference from the
polemics of modern and postmodern aesthetics, the battles to determine what is
“authentic” or “good” or “powerful” in twentieth-century art, and resituate the
issue in a rather different context,” (Mitchell 36). What is meant by this
approach is that within genre, context is a significant factor when
determining, with a postmodern scope, whether or not a given work has
self-reflexive qualities in the first place. Certain factors must be embodied
by a given work in order to be considered metatextual or metapictorial. These
can be formal or ambiguous qualities, and most of the time determining what
exactly these qualities are tends to be quite a subjective process, and it can
vary from person to person, or reader to reader. The way that this is done is
through the clarification by juxtaposition of “an account of pictorial
self-reference that starts outside the institutions of art and cuts across the
debates about modernism,” (Mitchell 37). Furthermore the “sublime” is brought
into question in regards to metatextuality and metapictorial images because of
the after effects that a text or a work of art may have caused, due to the
“dangers of self-reflective art,” (Mitchell 41). The lens through which the
postmodernist world views genre in relation to context and substrate is very
skewed. It is multifaceted, and it differs greatly with each individual and
their own experiences with text and art. To an extent, Mitchell describes this
sort of approach as a “parody of modernist” views, (Mitchell 43).
Moreover, I wanted to also discuss the formal qualities
which a meta-scope have given those of us in a postmodern society. “[Metapictures]
in the strict or formal sense, a picture about itself, a picture that refers to
its own making, yet one that dissolves the boundary between inside and outside,
first- and second-order representation, on which the metapictorial structure
depends,” (Mitchell 42). Clearly the explanation here is that metapictures
acknowledge themselves as existing. Metatext has the ability to do this as
well. On the other end of that spectrum, dialectical images and how their
“primary function is to illustrate the co-existence of contrary or simply
different readings in the single image, a phenomenon sometimes called
“multistability,”” (Mitchell 45). When dealing with multistable images, the
meta-scope becomes even more differentiated because “most multistable images
are not metapictures in the formally explicit way,” (Mitchell 48). Again, these
dialectical images and text in some cases are subject to change when given a
specific genre, context, and substrate. With regards to the metapicture
specifically, within our postmodernist readings we have come to look at a
“metapicture [as] a piece of moveable cultural apparatus, one which may serve a
marginal role as illustrative device or central role as a kind of summary
image,” (Mitchell 49). The viewer in this case, forms their own accord of the
situation, again all relating back to the subjective viewing individuals can
have. The reasoning for the “observer’s dialogue with the metapicture—do not
occur in some disembodied realm outside of history but are embedded in specific
discourses, disciples, and regimes of knowledge,” (Mitchell 48). First and
foremost, the aim of anything metatextual or metapictorial is as follows: “the principle
use […] is, obviously, to explain what pictures [or a text] are—to stage, as it
were, the “self-knowledge” of pictures,” (Mitchell 51). These pictures have “a
“life” of their own, talking and looking back at us,” and the same goes for a
work of written text, (Mitchell 57).
To enumerate, due to the hybrid nature of metatext and
metapictures, these concepts have become very interchangeable given their
particular presence within a certain context, genre, or substrate;
“metapictures [and metatext] are notoriously migratory, moving from popular
culture to science, philosophy or art history, shifting from marginal positions
as illustrations or ornaments to centrality and canonicity,” (Mitchell 57). The
ultimate interpretation and agency of a metatextual or metapictorial work is therefore
subjective to the individual who is viewing or reading it.
No comments:
Post a Comment
Note: Only a member of this blog may post a comment.